Monday, December 11, 2023

Boldness in Standing for Christ on the Campus: Challenging Stereotypes by Standing Out

 * Part of an email I sent to fellow Christian professors.

For your consideration....

I was looking again at an article by Baylor sociologist, George Yancey, "How Academics View Conservative Protestants" Sociology of Religion (June 2015).  Yancey's specialization (one among many) is the anti-conservative Christian bias found in the educational arena.  Here are a few quotations from the essay:
  • "A sizable body of research has demonstrated an anti-conservative Christian perspective among academics." (First sentence of essay)
  • "Professors in universities and colleges rate political conservatives negatively, and religious conservatives--particularly conservative Protestants like evangelicals and fundamentalists--even more negatively.  For example, Tobin and Weinberg's (2007) survey of 1,200 college professors found that 53% admitted negative feelings about evangelicals.  Yancey (2011) found that about 40% of professors surveyed said that they would be less likely to hire a prospective employee for their department if that candidate was an evangelical, and about 50% would be less likely to hire a prospective employee if the candidate is a fundamentalist.  This negative bias has ramifications.  One study indicates that conservative Protestant students claim everyday experiences of discrimination in academia similar to the levels of discrimination reported by traditionally targeted groups, like women and blacks (Hyers 2008).  Other research shows that this antipathy affects hiring decisions (Yancey 2011) and graduate school admission (Gunn and Zenner Jr. 1996)." (p. 2--note my page numbers are from a pre-print version)
  • "We argue that there are two possible reasons for the rejection of conservative Protestants by academics: symbolic boundaries and lack of contact." (p. 2)
  • "This propensity to envision themselves [the progressive critics of conservative Christians] in a culture war helps explain some of our respondents' critique of evangelicals proselytizing.  This proselytizing may be a threat to these scholars since religious conversion may generate more opponents to their political and social goals.  Thus it is not surprising that several respondents make negative comments about the evangelical desire to convert others... (p. 13)
  • "Certain respondents view conservative Protestants as a threat to societal well-being... They fear that evangelicals will win support for an agenda these academics perceive as dangerous." (p. 13)
  • "Academics are unlikely to personally identify with conservative Protestants or have many conservative Protestant friends.  This may lead to an ignorance of conservative Protestants that feeds into negative stereotypes toward that out-group.  Those with closer ties to conservative Protestants gave the most academic definitions and also have the most positive attitudes toward conservative Protestants." (p. 17)
  •  "Conservative Protestants are disliked to the degree that they are perceived as oppressors both now and in the past which helps explain why evangelicals are rated lower by academics than other proselytizing groups, like Muslims (Tobin and Weinberg 2007; Yancey 2011)." (p. 17)
  • Yancey speaks of a "silencing effect which keeps conservative Protestants 'in the closet.'" (p. 18)
  • The final paragraph of the article (and this, if I may interject, may be where the "money is" for us in terms of practical application):
    • "This silence reduces the potential of conservative Protestant academics to use intergroup contact to challenge common religious stereotypes in academia.  The detached, guarded manner in which they discuss their religious beliefs may create social comfort for other academics, but also helps those scholars maintain symbolic barriers toward conservative Protestants.  Thus, even when conservative Protestant academics act in ways that defy anti-religious stereotypes, their hesitation to openly embrace a conservative Protestant identity makes it harder for other academics to tie those actions to conservative Protestantism, which might create a cognitive dissonance about that stereotype.  Conservative Protestant academics' strategy for dealing with possible stigmatization may unintentionally reinforce a social atmosphere that perpetuates academic marginalization of conservative Protestantism." (p. 19)
I post these quotations, not to create a sense of fear, but, rather, to move us to greater boldness in expressing ourselves and our academic work as explicitly Christian.  This obviously requires wisdom and winsomeness but failure to do this ("openly embrace a conservative Protestant identity") may actually backfire and create a more negative effect in the long run (according to Yancey).  This is to start a conversation among us--not dictate a set of rules.  Toward that end, here are a few questions to ponder--and hopefully, we can ponder them together!  (Feel free to respond in this email thread)
  • Have you seen an anti-conservative Christian bias in your department or career?
  • In what ways (if any) do you see or sense your campus to have an environment which stigmatizes Christianity (or versions of Christianity)?
  • Have you ever self-censored your Christian identity at your campus out of a sense of fear?
  • In what ways could you manifest a greater boldness in self-consciously living out your Christian identity on your campus--before students, fellow faculty, and administration?

Christian Professors: Showing Yourself to Be a Christian to Your Students

 From the book A Grander Story: An Invitation to Christian Professors giving perspective on when Christian professors should let their students and fellow faculty know they are Christians.









Secular Thinkers on the Campus: Influencing Students

 A few quotations from secular thinkers showing the need for Christian professors to be salt and light on their campuses.



Monday, December 4, 2023

Coherentism: Problems

·      B1 is a belief with observational status within Coherent System A.

 

·      According to Bonjour, “the observational status of a belief [B1] can be recognized in a justified way from within the person’s system of beliefs, for only then could this status be used as a partial basis for the justification of such a belief, which then would allow such observational beliefs to appealed to for these various further purposes.” (p. 195)

 

·      B1 is justified by belief B2—“But for a coherentist, the basis for such a recognition can only be the further belief, itself supposedly justified by coherence, that a given belief has this status.” (p. 195)

 


·      But another coherent system with differing beliefs could also have beliefs within it which justify beliefs with observational status.  Think of Coherent System B with B1* which is justified by B2*.

 

·      “As long as it only beliefs and the relations among them that can be appealed to for justification, the beliefs that a specific observation has occurred is all that matters, and whether such a belief was really caused in the right way becomes entirely irrelevant.” (p. 195)

 

·      Thus, one cannot, on coherentism, “distinguish genuine observational input from this counterfeit variety.” (p. 195) 


·      The coherentist wants to allow for observational inputs but there is no guarantee that the observational beliefs link up a mind-independent world.  Coherence of beliefs is only internal to the agent.  There is not direct access to the world through knowledge by acquaintance as one might have on a foundationalist understanding.


This appears, to me, to be a powerful critique.  The initial plausibility of coherentism being able to accommodate perceptual inputs which create beliefs is only rendered plausible if a foundationalist understanding is smuggled in.  Once the inner consistency of the coherentism view is made clear—only other beliefs within one noetic structure can serve to justify other beliefs—then the problems as outlined by Bonjour are manifest.


Critique of Laurence BonJour's Indirect Representational Realism

 * A paper written for an epistemology class for Biola's MA in philosophy.

AN INDIRECT DEFENSE OF DIRECT REALISM BY A DIRECT CHALLENGE

TO LAURENCE BONJOUR’S INDIRECT REPRESENTATIONAL REALISM

 

Direct realism is motivated by pre-philosophical intuitions that seem to orient one’s beliefs in an external world with which one is in direct contact.  However, direct realism has fallen on hard times.[1]  Since direct realism is seen as problematic, this sets up a search for other views which are more philosophically defensible.  Laurence BonJour’s version of indirect representational realism is one influential version of representationalism.  The following examination of BonJour’s views will proceed in two steps.  First, I will provide a brief expositional outline of Bonjour’s views regarding indirect realism.  These include, (i) realist intuitions that motivate a belief in an objective, external world, (ii) the denial of direct access to this objective, external world, and (iii) the belief that any such access to this objective, external world must be indirect access via mental representations.  The second step will consist in an examination of some deep internal problems with BonJour’s views.  This failure of indirect realism, coupled with the acknowledged realist intuitions, will motivate a renewed examination of direct realism.  Although a full-fledged defense of direct realism is impossible in this short paper, the argumentation contained here will serve to clear away the option offered by BonJour, thus opening up avenues for a reconsideration of direct realism.

BonJour’s Indirect Representational Realism

            BonJour is a realist in that he affirms a mind-independent external world which a subject can access.  He acknowledges these realist intuitions when he speaks of “our 

ingrained inclinations to describe the experiential content in physical-object terms.”[2]  Later he refers to “the approximately commonsensical idea that my sensory experiences are systematically caused by a realm of 3-dimensional objects”[3]  A recognition of these realist intuitions will be important when assessing BonJour’s views since it is precisely these realist inclinations that will work against BonJour’s overall position.

            Although BonJour affirms realism, he denies the traditional notion of a direct realism.  BonJour summarizes the representationalist view under two theses:

[F]irst, that what is perceived directly or immediately in sensory experience is not ‘external’ physical or material objects, but rather entities that are mental or subjective in character—sense data or sensa, according to the most standard versions of the view; and second, that the only available (reasonably cogent) reasons deriving from perception for thinking that perceptual beliefs about the physical world are true depend on inference from facts about these directly perceived mental or subjective entities, i.e., from facts about the character and contours of subjective sensory experience, to conclusions about physical or material objects.”[4]

 

Thus, according to BonJour’s first thesis, what the subject has access to are representations of the world in one’s conscious states; there is no direct access to the external world.  Bonjour does speak of “direct comparison or ‘confrontation’ between a conceptual description and the non-conceptual chunk of reality that it purports to describe,” but he is quick to add the important caveat: “Such a confrontation is only possible, to be sure, where the reality in question is itself a conscious state and where the description in question pertains to the conscious content of that very state.”[5]

            BonJour’s second thesis regarding the inference from sensory mental states to the conclusion of an external world is also important.  Here BonJour must argue against Berkeleyan idealism.  To engage the specter of idealism, BonJour makes a distinction between analog and digital explanations.  As used by BonJour, an analog explanation attempts to explain the features of the world “by appeal directly to the basic features of the objects in the hypothesized world.”[6]  On the other hand, a digital explanation of the experience one is having is appeals,

“to the combination of (i) something like a representation of a world, together with (ii) some agent or mechanism that produces experience in perceivers like us in a way that mimics the experience that we would have if the represented world were actual and we were located in it, even though neither of these things is in fact the case.”[7]

 

An analog explanation, in this context, would mean that the sensory experience in the subject is being produced by an objective, external world.  Whereas the digital explanation would appeal to some distorting force or figure (i.e., a Cartesian demon or Berkeley’s God directly causing the sensory experiences without a corresponding external world).

From this distinction, BonJour argues that the digital explanation is less simple and by a principle “something like Ockham’s Razor” he argues that the analog explanation is the better one.

Problems with BonJour’s Indirect Representational Realism 

            BonJour’s position is fraught with two key internal tensions: (1) the problem of non-conceptual awareness and (2) no justified contact with the external world.  To 

understand (1) it will be important to understand a key dilemma that must be overcome.  The dilemma has its roots with Wilfrid Sellars’ challenge regarding the “myth of the given” but its articulation can be found in BonJour himself.  BonJour writes:

[T]he givenist is caught in a fundamental dilemma: if his intuitions or immediate apprehensions are construed as cognitive, then they will be both capable of giving justification and in need of it themselves; if they are non-cognitive, then they do not need justification but are also apparently incapable of providing it.  This is at bottom why epistemological givenness is a myth.[8]

 

With BonJour’s turn to foundationalism, he must answer this challenge.  He seeks to overcome this dilemma in the following manner.  Acknowledging the second horn of the dilemma, BonJour affirms that a non-conceptual (“non-cognitive”) phenomenon cannot stand in a logical relation, but it can be construed in a descriptive relation.[9]  He then argues that the non-conceptual phenomena in question here is of a special nature.  BonJour’s key move is described in this manner:

But in the very special case we are concerned with, where the non-conceptual item being described is itself a conscious state, my suggestion is that one can be aware of its character via the constitutive or “built-in” awareness of content without the need for a further conceptual description and thereby be in a position to recognize that a belief about that state is correct without raising any further issue of justification.[10]

 

This “built-in awareness” is, in his words, a “non-apperceptive awareness”—a non-cognitive awareness.[11]  

            It is here that BonJour’s view runs into conceptual difficulty.  What exactly is a non-cognitive awareness of a non-cognitive sensory content?  As Steven Porter aptly notes,

It would seem that a non-conceptual grasp of the non-conceptual content of a non-conceptual state is a conceptually empty grasp of conceptually empty content of a conceptually empty state.  This awareness is supposed to be conceptually described, but it is far from clear what the subject is aware of in a non-conceptual awareness of a non-conceptual state which can serve as the object of description.[12]

 

In seeking to avoid the dilemma described above, BonJour has attempted to use a philosophical notion which appears epistemically vacuous.  As Porter argues, “non-conceptual awareness is a contradiction in terms.”[13]  It would appear that conceptualized perceptual awareness cannot so easily be dismissed.

            The second major problem for BonJour is that his view does not end up justifying belief in an external world.  It is important to remember that BonJour is motivated by realist intuitions; internal sensory states are indicative of an external world of three-dimensional objects.  The basic move here is that one can inferentially move from internal representational states to an objective external world.  BonJour dispenses with alternative hypotheses (e.g., Berkeleyan idealism) by his use of analog explanations versus digital explanations.  The analog explanation of an objective external world is preferred to the digital explanations since digital explanations are arbitrary and not as simple of explanations.  In his critical analysis of BonJour, Steven Porter acknowledges that it is true that there is no reason to prefer digital explanation over another digital explanation and that it is true that is arbitrary to prefer a digital explanation over an analog explanation.  

But Porter accurately assesses the situation when he notes the following:

But it does not follow from these two facts that we now possess a non-arbitrary reason to prefer the quasi-commonsensical hypothesis.  Unless there is something in sense experience that calls for the quasi-commonsensical hypothesis over the others, the same arbitrariness would equally attach itself to the quasi-commonsensical hypothesis.[14]

 

BonJour is seeking to argue that the reason to prefer the analogical explanation of an external world as the cause of one’s sensory states is that the phenomenology of one’s internal sensory states suggests an objective external world.  But it is precisely here that BonJour’s representationalism cuts one off from the external world.  What reason, given only one’s internal representational states, can there be given to prefer one explanation (analog) over another (digital)?  Steven Porter uses a helpful example to show the philosophical problem inherent in BonJour’s view.

Let us suppose that we are watching a film and an image resembling the Golden Gate Bridge appears on the screen.  Some philosophically attuned, inconsiderate movie whisperer poses the question as to whether the image is actual footage of the Golden Gate Bridge or whether it is a computer-generated image.  In other words, did the Golden Gate Bridge itself cause the image on the film (i.e., an analog explanation) or did a computer cause the image (i.e., a digital explanation)?  Of course, the image itself bears features which closely align with the features of the actual Golden Gate Bridge and which do not closely align with the features of a computer.  But this fact does not give us any reason to prefer the explanation that the image we are seeing was caused by filming the actual Golden Gate Bridge over and against the explanation that the image was caused by a computer which was used to digitally represent the bridge.  Indeed, there is nothing about the image of the Golden Gate Bridge which would lead us to prefer one explanation or the other if all that we have access to is the image and both explanations are in all other respects equal in their ability to account for the image.  If, of course, we had independent access to the actual Golden Gate Bridge, we could compare the actual features to the features of the image on the screen, and perhaps determine whether the image is an analog or digital production.  But if we only have access to the feature of the image, any preference for the analog or digital explanation based on those features alone would be arbitrary.[15]

 

According to BonJour’s representational indirect realism there is no possibility of having direct access to reality by which to compare the features of the actual world with the features of one’s internal sensory states.  All one has are mental representations of the external world and analog and digital explanations can equally account for this mental representation.  Even if BonJour attempts to argue that his analog explanation is superior to the digital explanation of Berkeley due to simplicity, this argument can be overcome by noting that according to Berkeleyan idealism only one causal entity is postulated “while BonJour must postulate a multitude of physical objects, their properties, and the causal powers and relations essential to the quasi-commonsensical view.”[16]  Thus, BonJour is left without any rational preference for his analogical explanation.  In the end, “BonJour’s position leaves us with justified beliefs about appearances but without justified beliefs about the external world.”[17]

BonJour’s Caveat and Rejoinder 

            Granting realist intuitions and recognizing the internal tensions inherent in BonJour’s view of indirect representational realism, one might think that a reconsideration of direct realism would be in order.  However, BonJour argues against such a move in the following manner:

No matter how difficult or even seemingly impossible the representationalist’s attempted inference from subjective experience to the material world may turn out to be, this is not enough by itself to show that direct realism provides a better epistemological alternative or indeed that it provides one at all.[18]

 

BonJour argues that unless the direct realist can give a positive account of how perceptual beliefs are justified then the door is open for the representationalist view “as the only apparent contender in the field (phenomenalism aside), however allegedly problematic it may be.”[19]

            BonJour’s thought can be captured in the following manner:

(1) Realist intuitions motivate a belief in an objective external world composed of three-dimensional objects.

 

(2) Direct realism cannot provide a positive account for justified perceptual beliefs.

(3) No matter the difficulties, indirect representational realism is the only apparent contender in line with the realist intuitions of (1) above.

 

But the defender of direct realism could mirror this reasoning in the following manner:

(1) Realist intuitions motivate a belief in an objective external world composed of three-dimensional objects.

 

(4) Indirect representational realism cannot provide a positive account for justified perceptual beliefs.

 

(5) No matter the difficulties, direct realism is the only apparent contender in line with the realist intuitions of (1) above.

 

The defender of direct realism defends (4) by an appeal to the analysis offered above about the inherent contradictions and tensions in BonJour’s defense of his views.  Thus, (5) follows and provides the impetus to reexamine the details in defense of direct realism.  

 

Steven Porter accurately captures this dialectic.  After summarizing the key problems with BonJour’s views, he writes, “These problems seem to offer insuperable difficulties for representationalism.  But many have come at things the other way around.  Starting with the natural view of direct realism they find defeaters of it, which lead them to the next best thing from the realist point of view—that is, representationalism.”[20]  But this dialectic, as set up by BonJour, should be challenged.  Granting the realist intuitions of (1), which are affirmed by BonJour, and considering the deeply problematic tensions within BonJour’s indirect representational realism, this should motivate a reconsideration of direct realism.  It is beyond the purview of this paper to attempt to this larger project; it has been the more modest project to clear the field of BonJour’s defense of representationalism.[21]



     [1] For a series of arguments against DR with potential replies see Pierre Le Morvan’s “Arguments Against Direct Realism and How to Counter Them,” American Philosophical Quarterly 41 (2004), 221-234.

     [2] Laurence BonJour, “Foundationalism and the External World,” in Philosophical Perspectives 13, edited James E. Tomberlin (Oxford: Blackwell, 1999), 240.

     [3] Laurence BonJour, “Foundationalism and the External World,” in Philosophical Perspectives 13, edited James E. Tomberlin (Oxford: Blackwell, 1999), 244.

     [4] Laurence BonJour, “In Search of Direct Realism,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 69.2 (2004), 350.

     [5] Laurence BonJour, “Foundationalism and the External World,” in Philosophical Perspectives 13, edited James E. Tomberlin (Oxford: Blackwell, 1999), 235—emphasis added.

     [6] Laurence BonJour, “Foundationalism and the External World,” in Philosophical Perspectives 13, edited James E. Tomberlin (Oxford: Blackwell, 1999), 244.

     [7] Laurence BonJour, “Foundationalism and the External World,” in Philosophical Perspectives 13, edited James E. Tomberlin (Oxford: Blackwell, 1999), 244.

     [8] Laurence BonJour, “Can Empirical Knowledge Have a Foundation?” American Philosophical Quarterly 15.1 (1978), 11.  This formulation is found in BonJour’s “coherentist” stage, but he recognizes the problem in his later “foundationalist” perspective.  He lays out the same dilemma in “Foundationalism and the External World” (page 231) where he states, “It is this dilemma that has always seemed to me to be the most fundamental objection to empirical foundationalism.”  In this latter paper, BonJour is specifically seeking to meet the dilemma’s challenge.

     [9] Laurence BonJour, “Foundationalism and the External World,” in Philosophical Perspectives 13, edited James E. Tomberlin (Oxford: Blackwell, 1999), 235.

     [10] Laurence BonJour, “Foundationalism and the External World,” in Philosophical Perspectives 13, edited James E. Tomberlin (Oxford: Blackwell, 1999), 235.

     [11] Laurence BonJour, “Foundationalism and the External World,” in Philosophical Perspectives 13, edited James E. Tomberlin (Oxford: Blackwell, 1999), 233.

     [12] Steven L. Porter, Restoring the Foundations of Epistemic Justification: A Direct Realist and Conceptualist Theory of Foundationalism(Lexington, 2006), 82.

     [13] Steven L. Porter, Restoring the Foundations of Epistemic Justification: A Direct Realist and Conceptualist Theory of Foundationalism(Lexington, 2006), 83.

     [14] Steven L. Porter, Restoring the Foundations of Epistemic Justification: A Direct Realist and Conceptualist Theory of Foundationalism(Lexington, 2006), 84.

     [15] Steven L. Porter, Restoring the Foundations of Epistemic Justification: A Direct Realist and Conceptualist Theory of Foundationalism(Lexington, 2006), 85-86.

     [16] Steven L. Porter, Restoring the Foundations of Epistemic Justification: A Direct Realist and Conceptualist Theory of Foundationalism(Lexington, 2006), 88.

     [17] Steven L. Porter, Restoring the Foundations of Epistemic Justification: A Direct Realist and Conceptualist Theory of Foundationalism(Lexington, 2006), 88.

     [18] Laurence BonJour, “In Search of Direct Realism,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 69.2 (2004), 351.

     [19] Laurence BonJour, “In Search of Direct Realism,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 69.2 (2004), 351.

     [20] Steven L. Porter, Restoring the Foundations of Epistemic Justification: A Direct Realist and Conceptualist Theory of Foundationalism(Lexington, 2006), 98.

     [21] For attempts at the larger project of explicating and defending direct realism see the following: Pierre Le Morvan, “Arguments Against Direct Realism and How to Counter Them,” American Philosophical Quarterly 41 (2004), 221-234 and Steven L. Porter, Restoring the Foundations of Epistemic Justification: A Direct Realist and Conceptualist Theory of Foundationalism (Lexington, 2006).

Sunday, November 12, 2023

Christian Sexuality: 1 Corinthians 6,9-20

 A sermon I preached on 1 Corinthians 6.9-20 on "Christian Sexuality."  The notes I used for the sermon are posted below. (NOTE: The last part of the sermon where I examine the contemporary slogan "love is love" is not contained in the notes.)




Introduction

 

·      Series on sexuality

 

·      Our time  sexual anarchy

 

o   Our time considers itself  “Progressive” and “Enlightened”

 

o   Orthodox Christianity’s sexual ethic is considered:

 

§  Antiquated

 

§  Oppressive

 

§  Mere negation  “Don’t do ______________ !”

 

·      Nancy Pearcey (Love Thy Body, 156)

 

“When we make sexual decisions, we are not just deciding to follow a few rules.  We are expressing our view of the cosmos and human nature.”

 

·      Short series

 

o   Can’t say and do everything

 

o   Can’t answer every question and challenge to the Bible

 

o   Can’t provide every nuance and qualification

 

·      Issues of the CONTENT of the Bible on sexual ethics

 

·      And APPLICATIONS and ATTITUDES

 

·      Homosexuality and the differing roles of the church

 

a.    Prophetic role

 

                                              i.     To our culture 

 

                                            ii.     Focus: Ideas/philosophy that are ingrained in culture (entertainment, media, law, background assumptions)

 

b.    Protective role

 

                                              i.     For the purity of the church; listen to God’s word in faithfulness

 

                                            ii.     Focus: False teachers 

 

c.     Pastoral role

 

                                              i.     For the sanctification of those in the church

 

                                            ii.     Focus: Spiritual compassion, guidance, and growth

 

·      Focus  Pastoral and Protective

 

o   If we cannot articulate and defend and pass on the Christian sexual ethic in the church,then there is no hope of transforming the larger culture!

 

·      “To attempt to change culture by merely changing its laws is at best cosmetic.  Our priority is to change the hearts and minds of people.  This is slow, arduous work… That is, we must begin to reseed culture from the ground up, as it were, training and educating our own in terms of broader Christian worldview thinking so we are prepared to impart values to broader culture.  If we resist or ignore long-term efforts to educate and penetrate culture by changing the way people think, no amount of ‘godly legislation’—or evangelism, for that matter—will ever be able to change culture at the root.  It will be the equivalent of pouring Rose Lime Juice on cancer.”  --J. Daryl Charles[1]


 

1 Corinthians 6.9-11

 

·      Unrighteous will not inherit the kingdom of God

 

o   Eternal life is at stake

 

·      “Do not be deceived”  potential for deception on this point!

 

·      Sin list  10 items mentioned

 

o   4 (40%) are sexual in nature!

 

§  “sexually immoral” (ESV)  porneia

 

§  Adulterers

 

§  “Men who practice homosexuality”  2 Greek words

 

·      ESV footnote: “The two Greek terms translated by this phrase refer to the passive and active partners in consensual homosexual acts.”

 

·      Note on interpretation of texts that speak against homosexual activity

 

o   Revise the text  make it say something else; narrow the application

 

§  Example: exploitive same-sex relationship

 

o   Reject the text

 

“The task demands intellectual honesty.   I have little patience with efforts to make Scripture say something other than what it says, through appeals to linguistic or cultural subtleties.  The exegetical situation is straightforward: we know what the text says.  But what are we to do with what the text says?  We must state our grounds for standing in tension with the clear commands of Scripture, and include in those grounds some basis in Scripture itself.”

 

“I think it important to state clearly that we do, in fact, reject the straightforward commands of Scripture, and appeal instead to another authority when we declare that same-sex unions can be holy and good.  And what exactly is that authority?  We appeal explicitly to the weight of our experience and the experience thousands of others have witnessed to, which tells us that to claim our own sexual orientation is in fact to accept the way in which God has created us.  By so doing, we explicitly reject as well the premises of the scriptural statements condemning homosexuality—namely, that it is a vice freely chosen, a symptom of human corruption, and disobedience to God’s created order.”[2]

 

·      Gospel is part of Paul’s message here  verse 11!

 

o   Notice the Persons of the Trinity

 

o   Notice the elements of Salvation

 

§  Washed

§  Sanctified

§  Justified

 

o   Leads into our next section…

 

1 Corinthians 6.12-20   

 

 

1.    Detailed look at 1 Corinthians 6.12-20

 

a.    Problem: Behavior  Visiting prostitutes (v. 15)

 

b.    Problem: Theology/Ideas/Worldview

 

                                              i.     Faulty view of ethics

 

                                            ii.     Faulty view of eschatology

 

                                          iii.     Faulty view of the body

 

c.     Paul’s Response

 

                                              i.     Paul doesn’t just say, “Stop it!”

 

                                            ii.     He refutes the false ideas (theology) and argues from the gospel to the truth of proper sexual behavior.

 

d.     Corinthian Slogans

 

                                              i.     There are three slogans from the Corinthian church to which Paul is responding.[3]  

 

                                            ii.     ESV translation highlights two of the three by quotation marks but on the second slogan the ESV stops short

 

1.    ESV: “All things are lawful for me” (v. 12)

 

2.    ESV: “Food is meant for the stomach and the stomach for food” 

 

3.    Should add in quotation marks: “and God will destroy both one and the other.”

 

                                          iii.     Third quotation is in verse 18: “Every sin that a man commits is outside the body.”

 

 

Verse

Slogan

Idea

12

“All things are lawful for me” (2x’s)

 

Ethics

13

“Food is for the stomach and the stomach is for food, but God will do away with both of them.”

Eschatology

18

“Every sin that a man commits is outside the body”

 

Body

 

 

2.    Paul’s responses to the Corinthian slogans

 

a.    “All things are lawful for me” (2x’s in v. 12)

 

                                              i.     “Paul, you taught we’re free from the law.”

 

                                            ii.     “No ethical constraints on the use of my body.”

 

b.    Paul’s response: Christian freedom has limits (v. 12)

 

                                              i.     Limited by love  not all things are “profitable”

 

“So the ethical question we have to have ask ourselves is not merely, ‘Is this or that activity okay for me to do?’  The question is, ‘Will this or that activity be a help or a hindrance to my brothers and sisters in Christ?’”[4]

 

                                            ii.     Limited by lordship  “I will not be mastered by anything”

 

1.    Ultimate allegiance is to Jesus Christ!

 

2.    Not be “mastered”—lorded over—by another

 

c.     “Food is for the stomach, and the stomach is for food, but God will do away with both of them.” (v. 13)

 

·      2 Arguments here from the Corinthians perspective…

 

i.      Teleology (purpose) of the body

 

1.    Stomach is for food.

 

2.    Sex organs are for sex.

 

3.    Human body’s design reveals its purpose; if it’s “natural” it must be right

 

4.    Corinthians: “What could be wrong using the body according to its purpose?”

 

ii.             Eschatology  physical bodies give way to death

 

1.    “Since every person must ultimately die and lost their body to the dust, God must not care much about physical bodies… From this, the Corinthians concluded that the physical body figured very little in God’s moral economy.”[5]

 

2.    Corinthian perspective: “moral irrelevance of the body

 

d.    Paul’s response: Union with Christ and the resurrection 

 

                                              i.     Against their teleology argument

 

1.    “the body is not for immorality, but for the Lord, and the Lord is for the body” (v. 13)

 

2.    Paul could agree that the body is made for sex

 

·      But this is a subordinate end/goal

 

·      Ultimate goal of the body is for God’s glory  for God’s sake

 

                                            ii.     Against their eschatology argument

 

1.    Resurrection is the great hope for our bodies (v. 14)

 

2.    Our bodies have eternal significance!

 

                                          iii.     Further argument against both teleology and eschatology arguments

 

1.    The believer’s body is Christ’s

 

2.    “When the believer engages his body in sexual immorality, he is involving Christ’s own body parts in the illicit act.”[6]

 

3.    “one body with her”  Genesis 2.24 (v. 16)

 

“It must not be missed that Paul grounds his sexual ethic in Genesis 2:24.  When Paul (and Jesus, for that matter) sets out new covenant norms for gender and sexuality, he never appeals to polygamist kings such as David or Solomon or to polygamist patriarchs such as Abraham, Isaac, or Jacob.  For all the importance these Old Testament figures have in the history of redemption, Jesus and Paul do not look to any of them as the paradigm for understanding marriage.  Instead, Jesus and Paul look back without exception to the pre-fall monogamous union of Adam and Eve in Genesis 2 as the norm of human sexuality and marriage.”[7]   

 

·      (cf. Gen 2.24; Matt 19.5; Mark 10.7-8; 1 Cor 6.16; Eph 5.31)

 

e.    “Every sin that a man commits is outside the body” (v. 18)

 

                                              i.     Idea: only motives and intentions matter; the body is irrelevant

 

                                            ii.     “This is not to say that the Corinthians denied the possibility of sin.  Sin was possible but only on the level of motive and intention, and they refused to concede that these could be evaluated on the basis of the actions in which they were embodied.  Hence, ‘every sin which a man may commit is outside the body.’”[8]

 

f.      Paul’s response: the body is the arena of central importance

 

                                              i.     Body is the arena of sin: “the immoral man sins against his own body” (v. 18b)

 

                                            ii.     Triune God—Father, Son, and Holy Spirit—interact with the body!

 

1.    Body is a temple of the Holy Spirit

 

2.    Body is bought by Christ (by his blood)

 

3.    Body is to be used to glorify God

 

3.    Christian sexuality is about a bodily reality that interfaces with God and the Gospel!

 

a.    “Body”  8 x’s in 1 Corinthians 6.12-20

 

                                              i.     Our view of the body is a theological and philosophical issue

 

                                            ii.     Christian worldview has a distinctive view of the body

 

                                          iii.     Crucial concept for all that follows!

 

b.    The Triune God interacts with us as bodily beings

 

                                              i.     Our lives—including our bodies—are bought with the blood of the Son.

 

                                            ii.     Our bodies are a temple of the Holy Spirit

 

                                          iii.     All of our bodily and sexual existence is to be lived for the glory of God

 

c.     The gospel engages our bodies throughout time

 

                                              i.     Cross  bought by the blood (past)

 

                                            ii.     Spirit  indwelt by the Spirit (present)

 

                                          iii.     Resurrection  raised up (future)

 

Conclusion:  

 

·      1 Corinthians 6 chosen as our entry point…

 

o   For its content but also for how Paul reasons

 

·      Paul is reasoning from the Gospel—the center of the Christian worldview

 

·      Instructive for us

 

·      Sexuality tells a story or as Nancy Pearcey states again:

 

“When we make sexual decisions, we are not just deciding to follow a few rules.  We are expressing our view of the cosmos and human nature.”

 



     [1] J. Daryl Charles, Between Pacificism and Jihad: Just War and Christian Tradition (Downers Grove, Ill.: Intervarsity Press, 2005), 139.

     [2] Luke Timothy Johnson, “Scripture and Experience” Commonweal (June 11, 2007)—online: https://www.commonwealmagazine.org/homosexuality-church-0

     [3] Not all commentators agree with this analysis of the slogans.  For a defense of the use of slogans here see Denny Burk, What Is the Meaning of Sex? (Wheaton, Ill.: Crossway, 2013), 45-46.  For a more technical discussion see Denny Burk, “Discerning Corinthian Slogans through Paul’s Use of the Diatribe in 1 Corinthians 6:12-20” Bulletin for Biblical Research 18.1 (2008), 99-121—online: https://www.ibr-bbr.org/files/bbr/bbr18a05_burk.pdf

     [4] Denny Burk, What Is the Meaning of Sex? (Wheaton, Ill.: Crossway, 2013), 49.

     [5] Denny Burk, What Is the Meaning of Sex? (Wheaton, Ill.: Crossway, 2013), 51.

     [6] Denny Burk, What Is the Meaning of Sex? (Wheaton, Ill.: Crossway, 2013), 53.

     [7] Denny Burk, What Is the Meaning of Sex? (Wheaton, Ill.: Crossway, 2013), 53-54.

      [8] Jerome Murphy-O’Conner as quoted in Denny Burk, What Is the Meaning of Sex? (Wheaton, Ill.: Crossway, 2013), 56.